Last week, I wrote about my disinclination to
lump the people killed in Orlando together as “victims” of an armed madman’s
rage or even as "people" whose horrific deaths were somehow more
terrible than if they had been murdered in some less dramatic way as
individuals rather than en masse as a group. A number of readers took
issue, asking me if I really thought that there was something inherently demeaning
to each deceased individual in the suggestion that his or her death was more
awful than it would otherwise have been because of the numbers involved. Given
that I’ve said the same thing many times about victims of terror in several other
contexts—that, human life being of inestimable value, there is something
slightly off about taking context into account when evaluating the deaths of
innocents—I was slightly surprised by those responses. And yet, even now after having
rethought the issue over these last days, I stand by my original remark and continue
to believe that, had Omar Mateen killed one single person instead of fifty,
that person’s death would be no less awful to contemplate—and the loss to the
world no less acute—because forty-nine other people weren’t killed by
the same crazy person on the same evening. As I wrote last week, each person
murdered in Orlando was a world unto him or herself, a universe of history,
ability, intelligence, and potential. As the great Hans Fallada wrote, “every
man dies alone and on his own terms,” i.e., as an individual, as a person, as a
complete world.
That there is something perverse and demeaning
in the effort to evaluate the worth of a human life is key. Indeed, for most
Americans the whole notion of assigning a specific value to a specific person’s
life sounds like something connected to the slave trade in olden times, a
wretched, degrading effort that rested on the traders’ ability to maximize
profit by “correctly” determining the dollar-value of any particular man,
woman, or child put up for sale. (Just for the record, when the Bible discusses
the case of the naïf who pledges the value of a specific person to the
Temple, a pledge both ridiculous and so inherently sacred that it cannot
simply be set aside or ignored, it fixes the specific amounts to be paid based
on age and gender specifically to avoid the possibility of people
actually attempting to say what a specific individual is worth monetarily. I’ll
write about that very interesting chapter some other time.) When expressed as a
philosophical concept, the concept that life is of incalculable value sounds
relatively inarguable. But the corollary notion that the lives (and, by
extension, the deaths) of specific individuals can also not be
rationally or ethically hierarchized feels seriously less undisputable…at
least most of the time and in most contexts.
We establish such hierarchies all the time,
after all. There are more people in need of all varieties of organ transplants
than there are donors, and so must the regulatory agencies that supervise such
procedures establish a way to determine whose life among those in need, say, of
a new kidney or heart is more worth saving. The version of the famous “trolley”
conundrum that imagines the conductor of a runaway train having to decide
whether to steer a train he cannot stop towards a terminally-ill elderly man or
a healthy child is another good example: for all we claim that no one can
assign actual worth to any human life, it would be the rare person indeed who
would say that it doesn’t matter what the conductor decides because the
death of a centenarian suffering from an incurable disease with just weeks to
live is no more or less tragic than the death of a seven-year-old in excellent
health who could conceivably live on for eighty or ninety more years and whose
potential contributions to the world cannot yet even be imagined. And even if
some among us would argue that there is something inherently wrong in
saying that the life of a child is more valuable than the life of an elderly
person, then surely even they would admit that the situation feels different
when the numbers are ratcheted up sufficiently and the conductor’s choice is
differently imagined to present him having to choose between aiming his train
at a single old man and a group of fifty or eighty children. Or between
steering his runaway train towards an elderly man and his ailing wife, and
aiming it at a nuclear power plant that, if seriously enough damaged, could
conceivably spew radioactive material into the atmosphere and end up harming or
even killing countless thousands. In such cases, it feels possible to determine
the relative value of two sets of human lives without transgressing any ethical
boundaries. But how to do it and what criteria to bring to bear in making such
a decision—that is a different matter entirely.
Horrible things have happened in our world just
recently. An eleven-year-old girl from Bexley, Ohio, was killed earlier this
week when a tree struck by lightning fell on her cabin in a summer camp in
Bennington, Indiana. A little boy from Omaha died after being snatched by an
alligator from some shallow water at the edge of lagoon at the Walt Disney
World Resort in Lake Buena Vista, Florida. Fourteen boys and girls aged nine to
eleven, none of whom was wearing a life jacket, died when the raft they were
paddling around on in Lake Syamozero in the part of northwestern Russia called
Karelia capsized during a sudden storm. And all this has happened since the
horrific murder of fifty young people out for a night of carefree dancing and
flirting in Orlando.
To say that each of these horrific incidents is
each other’s precise equal because, the value of life being unquantifiable, the
loss of any life is a tragedy no different from the loss of any other life
sounds reasonable enough at first blush. But is that really how we feel? The girl
from Ohio was the victim of a terrible accident that, truly, none could have
foreseen. The little boy in Florida, not so clear: given that five alligators
were taken from the lagoon after the boy’s death and that the boy was
obeying the sole sign in the area that merely said “No Swimming,” a sign that
most parents (myself included) would easily take to mean that swimming is
forbidden but not splashing around at water’s edge, it feels as though there
must be some real responsibility of both the moral and legal varieties
to be assigned. Does that make the boy’s death more tragic than the girl’s?
When put like that, the question feels bizarre even to pose aloud. But agreeing
that a disaster none could have foreseen is different in kind from—and
thus reasonably deemed more awful than—one that could easily have been
averted doesn’t feel as though it constitutes a rejection of the
principle that no individual’s life can be judged more valuable than anyone
else’s.
The situation regarding the children in Karelia
make this point even more forcefully: this disaster happened at a holiday
resort in which the children were theoretically being watched over by
responsible adults, yet they were permitted out on a huge lake without life
jackets despite cyclone warnings being in effect for the region. (Four
adults, including the director and deputy director of the hotel and two
water-safety instructors have been taken into custody and will probably face
criminal charges in the matter.) So although it feels wrong to attempt, however
ridiculously, to determine which loss of life constituted the greater tragedy,
it also feels natural to categorize these horrors in terms of the degree
to which they could possibly have been avoided. In other words, attempting to
evaluate the pristine value of any human life seems wrong. But establishing a
hierarchy based on the degree to which a given individual’s death could have been
averted feels not only right, but reasonable and just. But is that what
we want to assert: that the loss of life can best be evaluated in terms of whom
there is to blame? The children in Russia died because the people theoretically
watching over them were inept and irresponsible. But what then should we say
about the dead in Orlando, none of whom died because of ineptitude or
incompetence on the part of others but who were gunned down in cold blood by a
murderer who knew exactly what he was doing? Does the fact that they were
brutally executed make their loss different in kind from the death of that poor
child in Indiana who died when a tree fell on her bunk?
In my opinion, the most reasonable approach to
these issues would be to agree that we can assign a degree of tragedy to deaths
based on the degree to which they could possibly have been averted without
contravening the basic principle that human life is possessed of incalculable value. But another idea suggests itself to me as
well: that, without attempting to evaluate the worth of lives, we can entirely
reasonably assign value to deaths based on the posthumous good they inspire.
And that brings me to my final example of a
young person who died last week: Mahmoud Rafat Bardran, a fifteen-year-old
Palestinian teenager in the wrong place at the wrong time as members of the IDF
opened fire on Palestinians who were attempting to murder Israeli civilians
driving west on Route 443 outside Jerusalem by throwing rocks and firebombs at randomly
chosen cars. The dead boy does not appear to have been among those attempting
to take innocent Israeli lives; he and some friends had gone swimming after
breaking their Ramadan fast and were returning home in a taxi when their
vehicle was accidentally hit by gunfire. To describe his death as a tragedy
does not require any specific moral courage; how can the accidental death of a
teenager not be deemed tragic? In that sense, he joins the others as innocent
victims of circumstance. But by mentioning such a politically charged death in
the same context as the others, I sharpen my earlier point: his life was worth
no more or less than anyone else’s, but the worth, so to speak, of his death
will be determined posthumously by the effect, if any, it has on the world.
There is already no dearth of individuals
lining up to assign blame. For some, his death was, to quote one Palestinian
official, a “cold-blooded assassination.” That seems to me an example of almost
grotesque grandstanding by someone prepared to stand on the back of a dead
child to score some political points, but to wave his death away as mere
collateral damage only works if you are prepared to share that thought with his
grieving parents, if you are prepared to say that the unwarranted death of an
unarmed teenager riding home in a taxi is somehow less tragic than the death of
an innocent murdered by terrorists while eating ice cream in the Sarona Market
in Tel Aviv.
The stories are not each other’s equivalents. The Palestinian boy was killed accidentally by
people behaving nobly in the defense of innocents, whereas the people at the
Sarona Market were killed by people behaving criminally and, to say the least,
ignobly. But, in the end, none of them deserved to die…and that’s my exact
point: no innocent life is more or less valuable than
any other, but deaths can be evaluated in terms of what they bring in their
wake.In most contexts, this pill feels easier to swallow because it doesn’t feel
like there could be another side to the story: who could argue against more
sturdy bunks in summer camps, more clear signage at resorts where alligators
might possibly be lurking near children playing in shallow water, or more
stringent safety training for people charged with watching over children in
boats or on rafts? In the context of the Middle East, however, nothing is ever
that simple. Still, what single incident could be more likely to move the
parties involved to seek and find a way peacefully to co-exist in the same
corner of the world than the death of a child? You could say the same about all
the other victims of terror or of the response to terror, of course, including
the victims of last week’s horrific shooting in Tel Aviv. But what if this specific
incident were somehow to bring the world to its senses? It feels unlikely.
It could hardly be more unlikely. But unlikely isn’t impossible…and with
that hopeful thought in place, I conclude my ninth year of writing weekly
with this, my 355th more or less consecutive letter to you all.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.