With
this letter, I would like to return to the topic of the two-state solution I broached
a few weeks ago but still have more to say about.
To
begin by stating the obvious, there is surely no axiom relating to the Middle
East more often repeated and more fervently believed—if not quite by all than
surely by most—than the one that supposes that peace in the Middle East will
only come when some version of the United Nations’ original Partition Plan of 1947
is somehow put into place, yielding the desired—if long overdue—dismemberment
of Mandatory Palestine into two states, one Jewish and one Arab. This truth is so often repeated, and in so
many different quarters and by so many people from such different political
camps and orientations, that it has acquired the feel of a basic truth, of being
the kind of foundational idea that one can damn someone, and not faintly,
merely by suggesting that he or she is only paying lip service to its
reasonability but doesn’t really believe in it or think of it as the sole
workable solution to what would otherwise be an insoluble problem. Actually to
reject it as unworkable foolishness is, in at least most non-extremist quarter,
unthinkable.
I’ve
spoken about the two-state solution in public many times and always positively.
But now that I force myself to revisit the basic concept and to consider the
parts before coming to judgment regarding the whole, I find myself surprised by
how many of the ideas that constitute those parts strike me as naïve, even
utopian, when considered on their own.
There
is, at any rate, something surreal about the whole discussion—the endless,
ongoing, passionate discussion—regarding the two-state solution, and
specifically because there actually are two states, one Jewish and one Arab, on the
territory of Turkish Palestine. But, of course, even that assertion is complicated and depends, at least in part, on how one
views the long-forgotten Transjordan Memorandum of 1922, the British proposal
ratified by the League of Nations in September of that year that allowed for
the dismemberment of Ottoman Palestine into two regions, both to be
administered by the British: the part west of the Jordan to be called Palestine
and the part to the east of the river to be called Transjordan. This would just
be so much boring administrative history, except for the detail, made explicit
in the memorandum, that the point of the proposal was specifically to prevent Jews from settling in Transjordan. Nor is this a point to
gloss over lightly, because it was as a direct result of that dusty memorandum
that the Partition Plan of 1947—the United Nations proposal that is the bedrock
upon which the two-state solution rests—only ever applied to the lands west of
the Jordan, the part that was called Mandatory Palestine. And so, because the
land on the east side of the river was excluded not because of historical or
geographical reasons but merely because the British perceived doing so to be in
their own best interests and got the League of Nations to go along with the
idea, today’s proponents of the two-state solution remain mostly unaware of the
undeniable fact that there actually are two states, one Arab and
one Jewish, on the territory that the world took from the Turks after the First
World War and gave to the British to administer. That, however, is not what I want to write
about today.
Nor
do I want to focus on the obtuse unwillingness of so many who speak vocally
about the two-state solution as the sole path forward to peace to take a long,
hard look at Gaza…and then explain why Israel should not insist on ironclad
guarantees that the citizens of some future state of Palestine will not follow
the Gazans’ lead and give their nation over to radical terrorists whose whole raison
d’être is the annihilation of the Jewish state. (For European nations like
Ireland and Sweden that face no existential threats from without and whose right
to live in peace on their own soil is contested by none to look past Gaza and
pretend not to see the problem borders on the grotesque. But I’ll return to that
set of ideas in a future letter.)
Instead,
what I would like to bring to the discussion today are two ten-dollar words
that denote related but distinct concepts, and which hardly ever appear in discussions
of Middle Eastern politics: irredentism and revanchism. The former, irredentism, denotes any popular
movement rooted in the desire to reclaim “lost” territory that the proponents
of the movement consider rightfully theirs. (The word derives from the Italian
word irridento, which means “unredeemed” and was coined in the 1870s by
activists who wished to “redeem” the Italian-speaking parts of Austria and
France by making them part of Italy.) The latter, revanchism, denotes any
political movement rooted in the desire to reverse territorial losses incurred
through war or through some other political process, and to restore them to
their original political status. (The word derives from the French word revanche,
which means “revenge” and was coined by French nationalists who wanted to
reclaim Alsace-Lorraine from Germany after losing those two eastern provinces
in the aftermath of the Franco-Prussian War of 1870-1871.) The Palestinian cause has elements of both,
of course: the “redemption” of Arab land that somehow ended up as part of
Israel and “revenge” both for the defeat in 1948-1949 that established
Israel as an independent country and left the West Bank in the hands of Jordan
and Gaza under Egyptian control, and also for the Arab defeat in the Six
Day War that left the West Bank, the Golan, the Sinai, and Gaza under Israeli
control.
Viewing
the struggle for an independent Palestinian state through the lenses of
irredentism and revanchism is an interesting experience, because it allows us
to view the whole situation through a much wider lens than usual. The
irredentist and/or revanchist claims of nations are, it turns out, countless.
But the world takes little note of most of them: the principle that law most reasonably
derives from facts on the ground—in the Latin of international law: ex
factis jus oritur—is broadly brought to bear to dismiss most irredentist
claims as nationalistic fantasies that cannot be expected to trump the actual
boundaries of existent nations. No one, for example, is prepared to take South
Tyrol from Italy and hand it over to Austria merely because there are Austrians
who haven’t made peace with its loss following World War II. Nor is the world
going to dismember the United Kingdom and hand North Ireland over to Ireland merely
because a large majority of Irish citizens think of it as an integral part of
their island-nation, which it surely is geographically, and because its
citizens are almost exclusively ethnically Irish. Nor did the world seek to
head off the first Gulf War merely by handing over Kuwait to the Iraqis who
claimed it as their own territory merely because the boundary between the two
nations was yet another British line arbitrary drawn, this time literally, in
the sand…much less because Saddam Hussein threatened war if they didn’t.
European nations alone with irredentist claims on other countries’ territory
include, aside from Austria and Ireland, Portugal, Spain, Hungary, Romania,
Croatia, Servia, Bosnia, Albania, Bulgaria, Germany, Lithuania, Poland,
Belarus, Ukraine, Norway, Russia. Asian nations with irredentist claims on
other countries include India, Japan, China, Afghanistan, Pakistan, Cambodia,
and the Philippines. The list goes on. (For a full list, click here.)
Indeed, as I reviewed these claims and was amazed not only at how many they
are, but at how many different nations they involve, it struck me that the
assumption so many of us seem to have that the mere fact of the Israeli
victory in the Six-Day War implies some sort of obligation on Israel’s part to
hand over land it has administered for half a century seems weak and not at all
in conformity with the way the world views other similar disputes regarding
territories lost in war or as a result of political adventurism abroad.
There
is a counterpart to the principle of ex factis jus oritur mentioned
above: it is ex injuria jus non oritur, which means that, for all law
must and should rest on a foundation of reality, “unjust acts cannot create law.”
That suggests a certain unsavory underside to the argument that Israel has some
sort of unilateral obligation to create a Palestinian state on the West Bank
when put forward by nations who themselves couldn’t be less interested in
creating “two-state solutions” in response to irredentist claims on their own
territorial integrity. (Just for fun, try suggesting to an Australian that
Australia solve its aboriginal problem with a two-state solution…or to a New
Zealander that New Zealand solve its Maori problem by divvying up the landmass so
that the descendants of the nation’s colonial invaders and those of the natives
they found in place can thrive in separate political entities.) Indeed, the
supposition that Israel’s existence itself is a kind of unjust act
perpetrated by the world on the Palestinians, an argument that has neither
historical validity nor philosophical merit, would justify the assumption that
Israel must cede land it won in a war foisted upon it by its enemies.
But that argument—that Israel is itself an unjustifiable aberration the
existence of which cannot be used as the basis to create law at all—is not only
offensive, but suggestive of a deeply anti-Semitic worldview.
I am
not arguing that the Palestinians should be made to pay forever for their huge
error of judgment in 1947 when the world offered them an independent state and
they specifically chose not to take it because taking it would have
meant living in peace with the Jewish state next door. But the assumption that
the facts on the ground cannot and should not create the law that governs the
parties to the dispute can only be sustained by arguing the illegitimacy of the
Jewish state…and that is a position that principled people possessed of an
unbiased sense of history may never embrace.
A
two-state solution may in the end be a good thing for all parties to the
dispute. I actually think that that probably is the case. But to argue
that it must be, that it is immoral and unreasonable for the Arab side to bear
the consequences of their own defeat in war both in 1948 and in 1967—that is
simply a principle of law that none of the nations of the world seems to apply
to itself. And that point—and also that Israel has every right never to
agree to any sort of agreement that could conceivably lead to the establishment
of Gaza East on the West Bank—those are the points that seems regularly
lost on most, including those who speak the most fervently in favor of the
two-state solution to the Israeli-Palestinian conflict.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.