Most of my readers surely know by now of my
predilection for murder mysteries, although for some reason mostly of the
off-shore variety by authors like P.D. James, Georges Simenon, Arnuldur
Indridason, Jo Nesbø, Colin Cotterill, Janwillem van de Wetering, Batya Gur, C.J.
Sansom, and many others. But today’s letter is about murder not abroad but at
home. And not the kind of murder
generally featured in the books of the above-named greats either.
If I were writing a dictionary, I think I
would define murder as the doing of some specific thing that leads directly to
the death of another person. Clearly, pointing a gun at someone’s chest and
shooting a bullet through his or her heart would qualify. So would feeding someone poison or pushing
them off the roof of a tall building. But other variations on the theme make
the concept feel murkier to me. In law, intentionality—that is, the question of
whether the defendant intended to take the dead person’s life—is a big
piece of the puzzle. But even that is a
complicated concept for non-lawyers like myself to negotiate: what, for
example, if the defendant can clearly be shown not to have intended to kill the
specific person who died but could or should have known that his or her
actions were inevitably or almost inevitably going to lead to the death of someone.
Since most—okay, all—of my legal training comes from reading the authors
mentioned above (plus the occasional John Grisham novel) and watching Law
and Order on television, I’m not entirely sure how qualified I am even to
have an opinion! Yet, even for a
non-lawyer like myself, the obvious questions to be addressed feel obvious.
What should the precise definition of “almost” in the expression “almost
inevitably going to lead to the death of someone” be? How long can or should the
chain of responsibility actually be before it becomes ridiculous to consider
someone even involved, let alone legally responsible, for the death of another?
How should the concept of awareness be folded into the batter? In other words,
how aware of the potential consequences of one’s acts should one need to be to
qualify as a murderer if those acts lead to the deaths of others? What if one
had no awareness at all? Is that an excuse? Should it be? And, if it should be,
then just how aware exactly does one need to be about the potential
consequences of one’s actions?
My first story has to do with one Stewart
Parnell, 61, up until just recently the CEO of the now-defunct Georgia-based
Peanut Corporation of America but about to spend his next twenty-eight years of
his life, supposing he lives that long, as an inmate in a federal prison. The specific
crimes with which he was charged are of the kind relating to interstate
commerce that non-lawyers will find it complicated to unravel, but the short
version is that the defendant was convicted of knowingly providing tons of salmonella-tainted
peanut paste (the main ingredient in peanut butter) shipped over state lines to
major customers like Kellogg’s with phony lab reports indicating that
salmonella screenings had been duly conducted and that the results were
negative. Kellogg’s and the other companies then used the peanut paste to
manufacture various food products (and not solely peanut butter) that they sold
under their own brand names. Yet email
records uncovered by federal investigators revealed unequivocally that Parnell
and other in his organization knew that foodstuffs confirmed by lab tests to
contain salmonella were knowingly shipped to customers. (Parnell’s brother
Michael was also convicted and sentenced to twenty years in prison.) The
results were, literally, sickening: more than seven hundred people in forty-six
different state were poisoned and nine died after eating foods made from peanut
paste that originated in Parnell’s plant.
Nonetheless, Parnell was specifically not tried as a murderer.
Indeed, U.S. District Court Judge W. Louis Sands noted in his remarks both
that the theoretical maximum number of years of incarceration to which Parnell
could have been sentenced was more than eight centuries’ worth and
that that was without him specifically being accused or convicted of murder.
Indeed, the judge’s word were explicit: “This is not a murder case,” he said
plainly. And, indeed, it wasn’t: the
judge was speaking as a jurist, not an ethicist, and was merely commenting on
the nature of the charges laid against Parnell, not extemporizing about the
nature of his ultimate responsibility for the consequences of his actions. Nonetheless,
let’s leave those words ringing in our ears as we move on to consider my next
story.
This one is slightly more far-fetched, yet it
too features people being killed but without there being any actual murderers
to prosecute. At a certain point,
General Motors became aware of a huge defect in at least some of the cars it
was selling the public: a defect in the ignition switch that effectively made
it impossible for the front passenger-seat airbag to deploy. Aware of the
seriousness of the problem, but apparently hoping the problem would somehow
just go away on its own, GM sold cars with these defective systems for ten
years after becoming aware of the problem. The results were horrific: 120
deaths and another 1385 individuals hurt seriously in accidents that were the
direct result of their GM car failing to operate as promised. As a result of a deal announced just a few
days ago by U.S. Attorney Preet Bharara, General Motors has agreed to pay a
fine of $900 million dollars…despite its official position on the matter
being that it admits to no actual guilt. Settlements with individual parties
are in the $575 million category. And on top of that is the cost, to be
carried solely by GM, of fixing more than two and a half million vehicles
sold under false pretenses when the company knew perfectly well that at least
some of them would not perform as advertised in the event of an accident.
A fine approaching a billion dollars
seems almost unimaginable to me, but it’s not the biggest fine ever paid out—it’s
less than the $1.2 billion dollars Toyota paid out last year to atone
for its sloth in dealing with the unexpected acceleration issue that plagued
some of its vehicles, for example—but it surely is an impressive one. Yet, despite
the fact that we are talking about specific actions that led directly to ten
dozen deaths, no one is apparently going to be charged with anyone’s murder in
this case either. Indeed, the New York Times reported the other day that the
plan now is not to press any charges at all against any individual
employees of General Motors. Let me quote from a September 16 article by Ben
Protess and Danielle Ivory: “After more than a
yearlong inquiry into the defect,” they wrote, “…federal prosecutors in
Manhattan and the Federal
Bureau of Investigation struggled to
pin criminal wrongdoing on any one GM employee. They concluded instead that the
problems stemmed from a collective failure by the automaker.”
As I keep reminding my
readers, I’m not a lawyer. Maybe even that’s my problem, the reason I can’t quite
understand how specific decisions can lead to more than a hundred innocent
people dying, many in the prime of their lives, without anyone at all being
indictable for their murder. (Isn’t that what it means when the government
decides not to prosecute anyone for murder when someone is killed, that it
cannot say that any specific person is personally culpable enough to be
convicted in a court of law? Nor do I fully understand how a corporation can be
responsible for its action without the actual people who made the decisions
that led to those actions being similarly responsible. Corporations are just legal
constructs, after all; only the people who work for them can actually make decisions.
Maybe it’s not such a bad thing that I’m not a lawyer.) But I do find myself
wondering how this story fits in with Stewart Parnell’s: he too did something
that led to the deaths of innocents, yet was not charged with murder. I get it,
obviously. Too many in-between steps. Too twisted the path from original deed
to end-result. Too many intermediaries. Too little like putting a gun to
someone’s chest and pulling the trigger. A line so curvy as by its nature not
to lead anywhere in a straightforward enough way to make reasonable the
hope for a conviction.
Other examples will sound even
more far-fetched. Daraprim, a drug I hadn’t heard of until last week, is used
in the treatment of toxoplasmosis, a parasitic infection that can cause
life-threatening problems for babies born to women who become infected during
pregnancy as well as to AIDS patients or others with compromised immune systems.
The reason Daraprim was in the news last week was because its manufacturer,
Turing Pharmaceuticals, increased the price of a single pill from $13.50 to
$750, thus bringing the cost of a year’s worth of pills into the hundreds of
thousands of dollars’ range. If someone stops taking Daraprim because of the
prohibitive cost—I should mention that the outcry was so intense that Turing
has agreed to lower the price, although without saying by how much—but if
someone were to be obliged to give up the drug and then actually did die
as a result…would anyone be culpable? Certainly not the CEO of a drug company
that manufactures a pill that someone could have taken but couldn’t afford to
purchase! Wouldn’t that be like suing restaurant owners if someone in the
neighborhood dies of malnutrition because they didn’t just give their food away
for free? But if someone does die as the result of a specific action
undertaking by someone else…how can no one at all be responsible?
These are philosophical, not
legal questions sensu stricto. Yet I find them unnerving to consider at
this time of the year particularly because I myself spend so much time trying
to feel not guilty about the consequences of my own actions if they are only
far enough down the pike from where I am standing for me not to feel really responsible…even
though it was my own action, my own decision, that led eventually to the
consequence I am trying so desperately not to feel responsible for or
guilty of. I understand the difference between moral responsibility and
legal culpability, and I also understand that being ethically responsible for
misery that you yourself didn’t cause but could have alleviated—which
intrinsically Jewish notion takes this line of reasoning even further
afield of the criminal justice system—is not the kind of value the courts
should or even could enforce. But as citizens of the world, we need to hold ourselves
to a higher standard…and not to suppose ourselves free of guilt merely because
we are so far along the chain of responsibility from the consequences of our
actions that no district attorney would dream of indicting us of any specific
crime. The legal system has its own rules
and its own goals to pursue. But as we move into the third third of our season
of judgment (the one that follows Yom Kippur and only ends finally with
Hoshanah Rabbah, the last intermediary day of Sukkot), we need to look past the
question of whether we could possibly be tried in court for some tragedy or
another that has befallen someone somewhere and instead ask ourselves what it
means truly and honestly to be responsible for the world and for the people with
whom we share our planet. The earthly courts have their own rules, obviously.
But that is specifically not the court in which we stand before God in
judgement during these holiday weeks…and that thought bears consideration too
as we move forward towards Sukkot.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.