Most
of the authors I’ve been reading lately who oppose the use of torture to
extract information from prisoners fall largely into one of two categories.
Some
understand the use of torture regardless of circumstances to constitute what
legal philosophers call a malum per se, something that is morally wrong “in and of
itself” in which moral wrongness inheres by its very nature, as opposed to the malum prohibitum,
which term references the act that is wrong only because it is prohibited by
law. (The law requiring people to drive on the right side of the road would be
a good example of that latter—a perfectly reasonable law that forbids behavior
no one would describe as intrinsically evil.)
Still
others, perhaps less philosophically inclined, oppose torture on the practical
grounds that they feel that it rarely, if ever, yields truly useful information
because it merely brings the individual being tortured to the point at which he
or she will say anything at all to gain relief and because information so
acquired is therefore highly unlikely actually to be accurate. As an example,
people in this camp point to the torture-obtained admission by Khaled Sheikh
Mohammed, the Pakistani national named in the 9/11 Commission Report as “the principal
architect of the 9/11 attacks,” that he had recruited black Muslims in Montana
to carry out future terror attacks, a confession that he later recanted and
which apparently had no truth to it at all.
To
help refine my own thinking on the matter, I’ve had recourse in the last few
days to two important works: Torture: A
Collection, an extremely interesting
and rich collection of essays published by Oxford University Press in 2004 and
edited by Sanford Levinson, a professor at the University of Texas Law School;
and a very long and detailed essay by Rabbi J. David Bleich called “Torture and
the Ticking Bomb” published in 2006 in Tradition,
the quarterly journal of the Rabbinical Council of America, the largest
organization of Modern Orthodox rabbis. (Used copies of the Levinson book are
available for purchase online for less than $2.50; to see Rabbi Bleich’s essay,
click here.) In the Oxford volume, I was particularly
taken with the essays by Miriam Gur Aryeh and Alan Dershowitz. But I’d like to
focus primarily today on Rabbi Bleich’s argumentation.
After
a long and very interesting survey of modern and pre-modern approaches to the
topic, he turns to a specific question of Jewish law, the one concerning the
ticking bomb mentioned in the title of his essay. He begins by noting that the
Torah’s commandment at Leviticus 19:16 to the effect that one may “not stand
idly by the blood of another” has been interpreted since ancient times to mean
that there is a legal, not merely a moral, obligation to come to the aid of
someone who’s life is in danger. And then he poses the question about torture
against the background of that concept by proposing a situation in which
terrorists have placed a weapon of mass destruction, say a “dirty” bomb or even
a more sophisticated nuclear device, in a public place where it will take the
lives of thousands if it explodes. And let’s imagine further than one of the
terrorists, one who is considered at least likely to know the specific location
of the bomb, is apprehended, but refuses to reveal what he knows. Is there a
moral limit to the amount of force that may be applied to extract that
information from such a prisoner?
There
are lots of ways to approach the question. Is it a matter solely of numbers? In
other words, the example above imagined thousands of lives on the line. But
what if it were tens or hundreds of thousands? What if it were millions? And
that is where the distinction between a malum per se
and a malum prohibitum comes into play. Is the prohibition of torture
a line that by its very nature may never be crossed? Or is it just a bad thing
that rarely produces good results and that the law therefore rightly
forbids…but which could be morally justified under certain specific
circumstances? The Romans used to say fiat justitia et pereat mundus (“let justice prevail even if the world be
destroyed”). Those words have a noble ring to them…but the acid test is not
whether you would learnedly cite them in a law school application essay but
whether you, who are on record as abhorring the use of torture, would dare say
them aloud to someone whose children are in the city where the bomb has been
planted and where it will probably, or even just possibly, explode if its
location is not discovered in time.
Rabbi
Bleich begins his analysis by introducing the concept of the rodeif,
the “pursuer.” According to Jewish law, when someone’s life is in danger
because that individual is being pursued by someone who appears intent on
killing him or her, it is deemed permissible to save the individual being
pursued even if the sole means available to do so requires taking the life of
the pursuer. This is how the mandate not idly to stand by the blood of another
mentioned above is applied in our sources: there is an absolute obligation to
safeguard life and, in a situation in which one individual is attempting to
kill another, it is not merely permitted but required to do what it takes to
make sure that the pursued party survives even if doing so costs the pursuer
his or her life.
In
the situation described above, the one in which the apprehended individual has
information about the location of the bomb, is that individual a rodeif?
What if there is no evidence that this specific individual did anything at
all—and certainly not that he armed the bomb or knows how to disarm it—but
merely might know where it is. Is that enough to make him into a rodeif
whose survival may be risked for the sake of saving others? That, Rabbi Bleich
maintains, is the question at the heart of the matter. The prisoners the CIA
waterboarded to make talk were not at that moment trying to kill anyone. But
they had information, or possibly had information, that could have saved the
lives of innocents. Does that justify doing what it takes to make them tell
what they know? (And, no, you don’t get to have a different opinion if the
innocents in question are your own children or other people’s.)
What
comes through in Rabbi Bleich’s analysis again and again is how complicated
this all is. When the prisoner is being tortured, there is often no way to know
in advance if he possesses any usual information at all. Nor is it possible in
advance to know if the information successfully elicited with have any worth.
Also in the mix is the understanding of our Torah that the prisoner also has a
sacred obligation to save human life. So getting such a prisoner to provide
information that could conceivably save thousands is somehow both an assault on
his physical being and a way of assisting him or her to behave ethically.
For
most of us, it also depends how the question is phrased. When asked if
torturing prisoners to see what they might know is morally defensible, for
example, I think most of us would easily answer in the negative. But when asked
if there should be limits placed on the CIA agents attempting to elicit
information that could potentially save the lives of, say, a thousand school
children, I think most of us would answer quite differently. Nor does this
inconsistency have to do solely with the number of potential lives saved. When
the question references physical pain, as in electrical shocks or simulated
drowning, some of us would condone torture and others would oppose its use. But
if the question were to be rephrased to reference sexual assault—for example,
if we were to be asked to approve of a female prisoner being repeated and
brutally raped to elicit information from her, even of the kind that could save
innocents—my guess is that most of us would refuse categorically to condone the
practice. Finally, Rabbi Bleich mentions the concept of hora∙at sha∙ah, the temporary suspension of the law. Americans will think back to the Alien and Sedition Acts of 1798, to Lincoln’s Civil War suspension of habeas corpus, and to the detention without trial of Japanese-Americans during the Second World War. But this notion that even the most basic laws may be suspended in times of great national peril is part of Jewish tradition as well and extends under certain circumstances even to the most basic prohibitions. So, in the end, the question really is whether the war against our nation’s enemies, particularly violent extremists like Al-Qaeda and the Islamic State, is enough to justify the suspension of our natural disinclination to condone torture as a “regular” means of eliciting information from our nation’s foes. Some will stick to the malum per se argument and say, with the ancients, fiat justitia et pereat mundus. But others will think back to 9/11 and recall that our tradition also teaches that saving even a single life is the moral equivalent of saving the entire world.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.